Contents 1 History and etymology 2 Nature and purpose 3 Methods 3.1 Direct proof 3.2 Proof by mathematical induction 3.3 Proof by contraposition 3.4 Proof by contradiction 3.5 Proof by construction 3.6 Proof by exhaustion 3.7 Probabilistic proof 3.8 Combinatorial proof 3.9 Nonconstructive proof 3.10 Statistical proofs in pure mathematics 3.11 Computer-assisted proofs 4 Undecidable statements 5 Heuristic mathematics and experimental mathematics 6 Related concepts 6.1 Visual proof 6.2 Elementary proof 6.3 Two-column proof 6.4 Colloquial use of "mathematical proof" 6.5 Statistical proof using data 6.6 Inductive logic proofs and Bayesian analysis 6.7 Proofs as mental objects 6.8 Influence of mathematical proof methods outside mathematics 7 Ending a proof 8 See also 9 References 10 Sources 11 External links


History and etymology[edit] See also: History of logic The word "proof" comes from the Latin probare meaning "to test". Related modern words are the English "probe", "probation", and "probability", the Spanish probar (to smell or taste, or (lesser use) touch or test),[5] Italian provare (to try), and the German probieren (to try). The early use of "probity" was in the presentation of legal evidence. A person of authority, such as a nobleman, was said to have probity, whereby the evidence was by his relative authority, which outweighed empirical testimony.[6] Plausibility arguments using heuristic devices such as pictures and analogies preceded strict mathematical proof.[7] It is likely that the idea of demonstrating a conclusion first arose in connection with geometry, which originally meant the same as "land measurement".[8] The development of mathematical proof is primarily the product of ancient Greek mathematics, and one of the greatest achievements thereof. Thales (624–546 BCE) and Hippocrates of Chios (c470-410 BCE) proved some theorems in geometry. Eudoxus (408–355 BCE) and Theaetetus (417–369 BCE) formulated theorems but did not prove them. Aristotle (384–322 BCE) said definitions should describe the concept being defined in terms of other concepts already known. Mathematical proofs were revolutionized by Euclid (300 BCE), who introduced the axiomatic method still in use today, starting with undefined terms and axioms (propositions regarding the undefined terms assumed to be self-evidently true from the Greek "axios" meaning "something worthy"), and used these to prove theorems using deductive logic. His book, the Elements, was read by anyone who was considered educated in the West until the middle of the 20th century.[9] In addition to theorems of geometry, such as the Pythagorean theorem, the Elements also covers number theory, including a proof that the square root of two is irrational and that there are infinitely many prime numbers. Further advances took place in medieval Islamic mathematics. While earlier Greek proofs were largely geometric demonstrations, the development of arithmetic and algebra by Islamic mathematicians allowed more general proofs that no longer depended on geometry. In the 10th century CE, the Iraqi mathematician Al-Hashimi provided general proofs for numbers (rather than geometric demonstrations) as he considered multiplication, division, etc. for "lines." He used this method to provide a proof of the existence of irrational numbers.[10] An inductive proof for arithmetic sequences was introduced in the Al-Fakhri (1000) by Al-Karaji, who used it to prove the binomial theorem and properties of Pascal's triangle. Alhazen also developed the method of proof by contradiction, as the first attempt at proving the Euclidean parallel postulate.[11] Modern proof theory treats proofs as inductively defined data structures. There is no longer an assumption that axioms are "true" in any sense; this allows for parallel mathematical theories built on alternate sets of axioms (see Axiomatic set theory and Non-Euclidean geometry for examples).


Nature and purpose[edit] As practiced, a proof is expressed in natural language and is a rigorous argument intended to convince the audience of the truth of a statement. The standard of rigor is not absolute and has varied throughout history. A proof can be presented differently depending on the intended audience. In order to gain acceptance, a proof has to meet communal statements of rigor; an argument considered vague or incomplete may be rejected. The concept of a proof is formalized in the field of mathematical logic.[12] A formal proof is written in a formal language instead of a natural language. A formal proof is defined as sequence of formulas in a formal language, in which each formula is a logical consequence of preceding formulas. Having a definition of formal proof makes the concept of proof amenable to study. Indeed, the field of proof theory studies formal proofs and their properties, for example, the property that a statement has a formal proof. An application of proof theory is to show that certain undecidable statements are not provable. The definition of a formal proof is intended to capture the concept of proofs as written in the practice of mathematics. The soundness of this definition amounts to the belief that a published proof can, in principle, be converted into a formal proof. However, outside the field of automated proof assistants, this is rarely done in practice. A classic question in philosophy asks whether mathematical proofs are analytic or synthetic. Kant, who introduced the analytic-synthetic distinction, believed mathematical proofs are synthetic. Proofs may be viewed as aesthetic objects, admired for their mathematical beauty. The mathematician Paul Erdős was known for describing proofs he found particularly elegant as coming from "The Book", a hypothetical tome containing the most beautiful method(s) of proving each theorem. The book Proofs from THE BOOK, published in 2003, is devoted to presenting 32 proofs its editors find particularly pleasing.


Methods[edit] Direct proof[edit] Main article: Direct proof In direct proof, the conclusion is established by logically combining the axioms, definitions, and earlier theorems.[13] For example, direct proof can be used to establish that the sum of two even integers is always even: Consider two even integers x and y. Since they are even, they can be written as x = 2a and y = 2b, respectively, for integers a and b. Then the sum x + y = 2a + 2b = 2(a+b). Therefore x+y has 2 as a factor and, by definition, is even. Hence the sum of any two even integers is even. This proof uses the definition of even integers, the integer properties of closure under addition and multiplication, and distributivity. Proof by mathematical induction[edit] Main article: Mathematical induction Despite its name, mathematical induction is a method of deduction, not a form of inductive reasoning. In proof by mathematical induction, a single "base case" is proved, and an "induction rule" is proved that establishes that any arbitrary case implies the next case. Since in principle the induction rule can be applied repeatedly starting from the proved base case, we see that all (usually infinitely many) cases are provable.[14] This avoids having to prove each case individually. A variant of mathematical induction is proof by infinite descent, which can be used, for example, to prove the irrationality of the square root of two. A common application of proof by mathematical induction is to prove that a property known to hold for one number holds for all natural numbers:[15] Let N = {1,2,3,4,...} be the set of natural numbers, and P(n) be a mathematical statement involving the natural number n belonging to N such that (i) P(1) is true, i.e., P(n) is true for n = 1. (ii) P(n+1) is true whenever P(n) is true, i.e., P(n) is true implies that P(n+1) is true. Then P(n) is true for all natural numbers n. For example, we can prove by induction that all positive integers of the form 2n − 1 are odd. Let P(n) represent "2n − 1 is odd": (i) For n = 1, 2n − 1 = 2(1) − 1 = 1, and 1 is odd, since it leaves a remainder of 1 when divided by 2. Thus P(1) is true. (ii) For any n, if 2n − 1 is odd (P(n)), then (2n − 1) + 2 must also be odd, because adding 2 to an odd number results in an odd number. But (2n − 1) + 2 = 2n + 1 = 2(n+1) − 1, so 2(n+1) − 1 is odd (P(n+1)). So P(n) implies P(n+1). Thus 2n − 1 is odd, for all positive integers n. The shorter phrase "proof by induction" is often used instead of "proof by mathematical induction".[16] Proof by contraposition[edit] Main article: Contraposition Proof by contraposition infers the conclusion "if p then q" from the premise "if not q then not p". The statement "if not q then not p" is called the contrapositive of the statement "if p then q". For example, contraposition can be used to establish that, given an integer x {\displaystyle x} , if x 2 {\displaystyle x^{2}} is even, then x {\displaystyle x} is even: Suppose x {\displaystyle x} is not even. Then x {\displaystyle x} is odd. The product of two odd numbers is odd, hence x 2 = x ⋅ x {\displaystyle x^{2}=x\cdot x} is odd. Thus x {\displaystyle x} is not even. Thus, if x 2 {\displaystyle x^{2}} is even, the supposition must be false, so x {\displaystyle x} has to be even. Proof by contradiction[edit] Main article: Proof by contradiction In proof by contradiction (also known as reductio ad absurdum, Latin for "by reduction to the absurd"), it is shown that if some statement were true, a logical contradiction occurs, hence the statement must be false. A famous example of proof by contradiction shows that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is an irrational number: Suppose that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} were a rational number, so by definition 2 = a b {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}={a \over b}} where a and b are non-zero integers with no common factor. (If there is a common factor, divide both numerator and denominator by that factor to remove it, and repeat until no common factor remains. By the method of infinite descent, this process must terminate.) Thus, b 2 = a {\displaystyle b{\sqrt {2}}=a} . Squaring both sides yields 2b2 = a2. Since 2 divides the left hand side, 2 must also divide the right hand side (otherwise an even number would equal an odd number). So a2 is even, which implies that a must also be even. So we can write a = 2c, where c is also an integer. Substitution into the original equation yields 2b2 = (2c)2 = 4c2. Dividing both sides by 2 yields b2 = 2c2. But then, by the same argument as before, 2 divides b2, so b must be even. However, if a and b are both even, they have a common factor, namely 2. This contradicts our initial supposition, so we are forced to conclude that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is an irrational number. Proof by construction[edit] Main article: Proof by construction Proof by construction, or proof by example, is the construction of a concrete example with a property to show that something having that property exists. Joseph Liouville, for instance, proved the existence of transcendental numbers by constructing an explicit example. It can also be used to construct a counterexample to disprove a proposition that all elements have a certain property. Proof by exhaustion[edit] Main article: Proof by exhaustion In proof by exhaustion, the conclusion is established by dividing it into a finite number of cases and proving each one separately. The number of cases sometimes can become very large. For example, the first proof of the four color theorem was a proof by exhaustion with 1,936 cases. This proof was controversial because the majority of the cases were checked by a computer program, not by hand. The shortest known proof of the four color theorem as of 2011[update] still has over 600 cases. Probabilistic proof[edit] Main article: Probabilistic method A probabilistic proof is one in which an example is shown to exist, with certainty, by using methods of probability theory. Probabilistic proof, like proof by construction, is one of many ways to show existence theorems. This is not to be confused with an argument that a theorem is 'probably' true, a 'plausibility argument'. The work on the Collatz conjecture shows how far plausibility is from genuine proof.[17] Combinatorial proof[edit] Main article: Combinatorial proof A combinatorial proof establishes the equivalence of different expressions by showing that they count the same object in different ways. Often a bijection between two sets is used to show that the expressions for their two sizes are equal. Alternatively, a double counting argument provides two different expressions for the size of a single set, again showing that the two expressions are equal. Nonconstructive proof[edit] Main article: Nonconstructive proof A nonconstructive proof establishes that a mathematical object with a certain property exists without explaining how such an object can be found. Often, this takes the form of a proof by contradiction in which the nonexistence of the object is proved to be impossible. In contrast, a constructive proof establishes that a particular object exists by providing a method of finding it. A famous example of a nonconstructive proof shows that there exist two irrational numbers a and b such that a b {\displaystyle a^{b}} is a rational number: Either 2 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}^{\sqrt {2}}} is a rational number and we are done (take a = b = 2 {\displaystyle a=b={\sqrt {2}}} ), or 2 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}^{\sqrt {2}}} is irrational so we can write a = 2 2 {\displaystyle a={\sqrt {2}}^{\sqrt {2}}} and b = 2 {\displaystyle b={\sqrt {2}}} . This then gives ( 2 2 ) 2 = 2 2 = 2 {\displaystyle \left({\sqrt {2}}^{\sqrt {2}}\right)^{\sqrt {2}}={\sqrt {2}}^{2}=2} , which is thus a rational of the form a b . {\displaystyle a^{b}.} Statistical proofs in pure mathematics[edit] Main article: Statistical proof The expression "statistical proof" may be used technically or colloquially in areas of pure mathematics, such as involving cryptography, chaotic series, and probabilistic or analytic number theory.[18][19][20] It is less commonly used to refer to a mathematical proof in the branch of mathematics known as mathematical statistics. See also "Statistical proof using data" section below. Computer-assisted proofs[edit] Main article: Computer-assisted proof Until the twentieth century it was assumed that any proof could, in principle, be checked by a competent mathematician to confirm its validity.[7] However, computers are now used both to prove theorems and to carry out calculations that are too long for any human or team of humans to check; the first proof of the four color theorem is an example of a computer-assisted proof. Some mathematicians are concerned that the possibility of an error in a computer program or a run-time error in its calculations calls the validity of such computer-assisted proofs into question. In practice, the chances of an error invalidating a computer-assisted proof can be reduced by incorporating redundancy and self-checks into calculations, and by developing multiple independent approaches and programs. Errors can never be completely ruled out in case of verification of a proof by humans either, especially if the proof contains natural language and requires deep mathematical insight.


Undecidable statements[edit] A statement that is neither provable nor disprovable from a set of axioms is called undecidable (from those axioms). One example is the parallel postulate, which is neither provable nor refutable from the remaining axioms of Euclidean geometry. Mathematicians have shown there are many statements that are neither provable nor disprovable in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), the standard system of set theory in mathematics (assuming that ZFC is consistent); see list of statements undecidable in ZFC. Gödel's (first) incompleteness theorem shows that many axiom systems of mathematical interest will have undecidable statements.


Heuristic mathematics and experimental mathematics[edit] Main article: Experimental mathematics While early mathematicians such as Eudoxus of Cnidus did not use proofs, from Euclid to the foundational mathematics developments of the late 19th and 20th centuries, proofs were an essential part of mathematics.[21] With the increase in computing power in the 1960s, significant work began to be done investigating mathematical objects outside of the proof-theorem framework,[22] in experimental mathematics. Early pioneers of these methods intended the work ultimately to be embedded in a classical proof-theorem framework, e.g. the early development of fractal geometry,[23] which was ultimately so embedded.


Related concepts[edit] Visual proof[edit] Although not a formal proof, a visual demonstration of a mathematical theorem is sometimes called a "proof without words". The left-hand picture below is an example of a historic visual proof of the Pythagorean theorem in the case of the (3,4,5) triangle. Visual proof for the (3, 4, 5) triangle as in the Zhoubi Suanjing 500–200 BC. Animated visual proof for the Pythagorean theorem by rearrangement. A second animated proof of the Pythagorean theorem. Some illusory visual proofs, such as the missing square puzzle, can be constructed in a way which appear to prove a supposed mathematical fact but only do so under the presence of tiny errors (for example, supposedly straight lines which actually bend slightly) which are unnoticeable until the entire picture is closely examined, with lengths and angles precisely measured or calculated. Elementary proof[edit] Main article: Elementary proof An elementary proof is a proof which only uses basic techniques. More specifically, the term is used in number theory to refer to proofs that make no use of complex analysis. For some time it was thought that certain theorems, like the prime number theorem, could only be proved using "higher" mathematics. However, over time, many of these results have been reproved using only elementary techniques. Two-column proof[edit] A two-column proof published in 1913 A particular way of organising a proof using two parallel columns is often used in elementary geometry classes in the United States.[24] The proof is written as a series of lines in two columns. In each line, the left-hand column contains a proposition, while the right-hand column contains a brief explanation of how the corresponding proposition in the left-hand column is either an axiom, a hypothesis, or can be logically derived from previous propositions. The left-hand column is typically headed "Statements" and the right-hand column is typically headed "Reasons".[25] Colloquial use of "mathematical proof"[edit] The expression "mathematical proof" is used by lay people to refer to using mathematical methods or arguing with mathematical objects, such as numbers, to demonstrate something about everyday life, or when data used in an argument is numerical. It is sometimes also used to mean a "statistical proof" (below), especially when used to argue from data. Statistical proof using data[edit] Main article: Statistical proof "Statistical proof" from data refers to the application of statistics, data analysis, or Bayesian analysis to infer propositions regarding the probability of data. While using mathematical proof to establish theorems in statistics, it is usually not a mathematical proof in that the assumptions from which probability statements are derived require empirical evidence from outside mathematics to verify. In physics, in addition to statistical methods, "statistical proof" can refer to the specialized mathematical methods of physics applied to analyze data in a particle physics experiment or observational study in physical cosmology. "Statistical proof" may also refer to raw data or a convincing diagram involving data, such as scatter plots, when the data or diagram is adequately convincing without further analysis. Inductive logic proofs and Bayesian analysis[edit] Main articles: Inductive logic and Bayesian analysis Proofs using inductive logic, while considered mathematical in nature, seek to establish propositions with a degree of certainty, which acts in a similar manner to probability, and may be less than full certainty. Inductive logic should not be confused with mathematical induction. Bayesian analysis uses Bayes' theorem to update a person's assessment of likelihoods of hypotheses when new evidence or information is acquired. Proofs as mental objects[edit] Main articles: Psychologism and Language of thought Psychologism views mathematical proofs as psychological or mental objects. Mathematician philosophers, such as Leibniz, Frege, and Carnap have variously criticized this view and attempted to develop a semantics for what they considered to be the language of thought, whereby standards of mathematical proof might be applied to empirical science.[citation needed] Influence of mathematical proof methods outside mathematics[edit] Philosopher-mathematicians such as Spinoza have attempted to formulate philosophical arguments in an axiomatic manner, whereby mathematical proof standards could be applied to argumentation in general philosophy. Other mathematician-philosophers have tried to use standards of mathematical proof and reason, without empiricism, to arrive at statements outside of mathematics, but having the certainty of propositions deduced in a mathematical proof, such as Descartes' cogito argument.


Ending a proof[edit] Main article: Q.E.D. Sometimes, the abbreviation "Q.E.D." is written to indicate the end of a proof. This abbreviation stands for "Quod Erat Demonstrandum", which is Latin for "that which was to be demonstrated". A more common[citation needed] alternative is to use a square or a rectangle, such as □ or ∎, known as a "tombstone" or "halmos" after its eponym Paul Halmos. Often, "which was to be shown" is verbally stated when writing "QED", "□", or "∎" during an oral presentation.


See also[edit] Logic portal Mathematics portal Automated theorem proving Invalid proof List of incomplete proofs List of long proofs List of mathematical proofs Nonconstructive proof Proof by intimidation Termination analysis What the Tortoise Said to Achilles


References[edit] ^ Bill Casselman. "One of the Oldest Extant Diagrams from Euclid". University of British Columbia. Retrieved 2008-09-26.  ^ Clapham, C. & Nicholson, JN. The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Mathematics, Fourth edition. A statement whose truth is either to be taken as self-evident or to be assumed. Certain areas of mathematics involve choosing a set of axioms and discovering what results can be derived from them, providing proofs for the theorems that are obtained.  ^ Cupillari, Antonella. The Nuts and Bolts of Proofs. Academic Press, 2001. Page 3. ^ Gossett, Eric. Discrete Mathematics with Proof. John Wiley and Sons, 2009. Definition 3.1 page 86. ISBN 0-470-45793-7 ^ New Shorter Oxford English Dictionary, 1993, OUP, Oxford. ^ The Emergence of Probability, Ian Hacking ^ a b The History and Concept of Mathematical Proof, Steven G. Krantz. 1. February 5, 2007 ^ Kneale, p. 2 ^ Howard Eves, An Introduction to the History of Mathematics, Saunders, 1990, ISBN 0-03-029558-0 p. 141: "No work, except The Bible, has been more widely used...." ^ Matvievskaya, Galina (1987), "The Theory of Quadratic Irrationals in Medieval Oriental Mathematics", Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 500: 253–277 [260], doi:10.1111/j.1749-6632.1987.tb37206.x  ^ Eder, Michelle (2000), Views of Euclid's Parallel Postulate in Ancient Greece and in Medieval Islam, Rutgers University, retrieved 2008-01-23  ^ Buss, Samuel R. (1998), "An introduction to proof theory", in Buss, Samuel R., Handbook of Proof Theory, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 137, Elsevier, pp. 1–78, ISBN 9780080533186 . See in particular p. 3: "The study of Proof Theory is traditionally motivated by the problem of formalizing mathematical proofs; the original formulation of first-order logic by Frege [1879] was the first successful step in this direction." ^ Cupillari, page 20. ^ Cupillari, page 46. ^ Examples of simple proofs by mathematical induction for all natural numbers ^ Proof by induction, University of Warwick Glossary of Mathematical Terminology ^ While most mathematicians do not think that probabilistic evidence ever counts as a genuine mathematical proof, a few mathematicians and philosophers have argued that at least some types of probabilistic evidence (such as Rabin's probabilistic algorithm for testing primality) are as good as genuine mathematical proofs. See, for example, Davis, Philip J. (1972), "Fidelity in Mathematical Discourse: Is One and One Really Two?" American Mathematical Monthly 79:252-63. Fallis, Don (1997), "The Epistemic Status of Probabilistic Proof." Journal of Philosophy 94:165-86. ^ "in number theory and commutative algebra... in particular the statistical proof of the lemma." [1] ^ "Whether constant π (i.e., pi) is normal is a confusing problem without any strict theoretical demonstration except for some statistical proof"" (Derogatory use.)[2] ^ "these observations suggest a statistical proof of Goldbach's conjecture with very quickly vanishing probability of failure for large E" [3] ^ "What to do with the pictures? Two thoughts surfaced: the first was that they were unpublishable in the standard way, there were no theorems only very suggestive pictures. They furnished convincing evidence for many conjectures and lures to further exploration, but theorems were coins of the realm ant the conventions of that day dictated that journals only published theorems", David Mumford, Caroline Series and David Wright, Indra's Pearls, 2002 ^ "Mandelbrot, working at the IBM Research Laboratory, did some computer simulations for these sets on the reasonable assumption that, if you wanted to prove something, it might be helpful to know the answer ahead of time."A Note on the History of Fractals Archived 2009-02-15 at the Wayback Machine., ^ "... brought home again to Benoit [Mandelbrot] that there was a 'mathematics of the eye', that visualization of a problem was as valid a method as any for finding a solution. Amazingly, he found himself alone with this conjecture. The teaching of mathematics in France was dominated by a handful of dogmatic mathematicians hiding behind the pseudonym 'Bourbaki'... ", Introducing Fractal Geometry, Nigel Lesmoir-Gordon ^ Patricio G. Herbst, Establishing a Custom of Proving in American School Geometry: Evolution of the Two-Column Proof in the Early Twentieth Century, Educational Studies in Mathematics, Vol. 49, No. 3 (2002), pp. 283-312, ^ Introduction to the Two-Column Proof, Carol Fisher


Sources[edit] Pólya, G. (1954), Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning, Princeton University Press . Fallis, Don (2002), "What Do Mathematicians Want? Probabilistic Proofs and the Epistemic Goals of Mathematicians", Logique et Analyse, 45: 373–388 . Franklin, J.; Daoud, A. (2011), Proof in Mathematics: An Introduction, Kew Books, ISBN 0-646-54509-4 . Solow, D. (2004), How to Read and Do Proofs: An Introduction to Mathematical Thought Processes, Wiley, ISBN 0-471-68058-3 . Velleman, D. (2006), How to Prove It: A Structured Approach, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-67599-5 .


External links[edit] Look up proof in Wiktionary, the free dictionary. Proofs in Mathematics: Simple, Charming and Fallacious A lesson about proofs, in a course from Wikiversity v t e Logic Outline History Fields Argumentation theory Axiology Critical thinking Logic in computer science Mathematical logic Metalogic Metamathematics Non-classical logic Philosophical logic Philosophy of logic Set theory Foundations Abduction Analytic and synthetic propositions Antinomy A priori and a posteriori Deduction Definition Description Induction Inference Logical form Logical consequence Logical truth Name Necessity and sufficiency Meaning Paradox Possible world Presupposition Probability Reason Reference Semantics Statement Strict implication Substitution Syntax Truth Validity Lists topics Mathematical logic Boolean algebra Set theory other Logicians Rules of inference Paradoxes Fallacies Logic symbols Portal Category WikiProject (talk) changes Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Mathematical_proof&oldid=810653620" Categories: Mathematical logicMathematical terminologyMathematical proofsSources of knowledgeHidden categories: Webarchive template wayback linksArticles containing potentially dated statements from 2011All articles containing potentially dated statementsAll articles with unsourced statementsArticles with unsourced statements from November 2014Articles with unsourced statements from October 2017


Navigation menu Personal tools Not logged inTalkContributionsCreate accountLog in Namespaces ArticleTalk Variants Views ReadEditView history More Search Navigation Main pageContentsFeatured contentCurrent eventsRandom articleDonate to WikipediaWikipedia store Interaction HelpAbout WikipediaCommunity portalRecent changesContact page Tools What links hereRelated changesUpload fileSpecial pagesPermanent linkPage informationWikidata itemCite this page Print/export Create a bookDownload as PDFPrintable version In other projects Wikimedia CommonsWikibooks Languages AfrikaansAlemannischالعربيةAragonésAsturianuAzərbaycancaBân-lâm-gúБашҡортсаБеларускаяБеларуская (тарашкевіца)‎БългарскиBosanskiCatalàČeštinaDanskDeutschΕλληνικάEspañolEsperantoفارسیFrançaisGalego贛語한국어हिन्दीHrvatskiBahasa IndonesiaÍslenskaItalianoעבריתქართულიҚазақшаLatinaLatviešuLietuviųLa .lojban.MagyarМакедонскиമലയാളംBahasa MelayuNederlands日本語NordfriiskNorskNorsk nynorskOccitanਪੰਜਾਬੀپنجابیPatoisPlattdüütschPolskiPortuguêsRomânăРусиньскыйРусскийScotsSicilianuසිංහලSimple EnglishSlovenčinaSlovenščinaСрпски / srpskiSrpskohrvatski / српскохрватскиSuomiSvenskaTagalogதமிழ்Татарча/tatarçaไทยTürkçeУкраїнськаاردوTiếng Việt文言Winarayייִדיש粵語Žemaitėška中文 Edit links This page was last edited on 16 November 2017, at 16:26. Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization. Privacy policy About Wikipedia Disclaimers Contact Wikipedia Developers Cookie statement Mobile view (window.RLQ=window.RLQ||[]).push(function(){mw.config.set({"wgPageParseReport":{"limitreport":{"cputime":"0.352","walltime":"0.539","ppvisitednodes":{"value":2787,"limit":1000000},"ppgeneratednodes":{"value":0,"limit":1500000},"postexpandincludesize":{"value":54816,"limit":2097152},"templateargumentsize":{"value":4121,"limit":2097152},"expansiondepth":{"value":16,"limit":40},"expensivefunctioncount":{"value":3,"limit":500},"entityaccesscount":{"value":0,"limit":400},"timingprofile":["100.00% 346.054 1 -total"," 41.30% 142.906 1 Template:Reflist"," 14.17% 49.042 2 Template:Citation_needed"," 14.11% 48.831 8 Template:Citation"," 12.79% 44.273 2 Template:Fix"," 11.52% 39.872 2 Template:Isbn"," 10.39% 35.961 1 Template:Cite_web"," 7.42% 25.675 4 Template:Category_handler"," 5.95% 20.574 1 Template:See_also"," 5.31% 18.378 17 Template:Main"]},"scribunto":{"limitreport-timeusage":{"value":"0.129","limit":"10.000"},"limitreport-memusage":{"value":5055790,"limit":52428800}},"cachereport":{"origin":"mw1247","timestamp":"20180115182137","ttl":1900800,"transientcontent":false}}});});(window.RLQ=window.RLQ||[]).push(function(){mw.config.set({"wgBackendResponseTime":101,"wgHostname":"mw1255"});});


Mathematical_proof - Photos and All Basic Informations

Mathematical_proof More Links

EnlargePapyrus Oxyrhynchus 29MathematicsPropositionArgument-deduction-proof DistinctionsTheoremsAxiomInferenceDeductive ReasoningInductive ReasoningEmpirical EvidenceInductive ReasoningConjectureLogicNatural LanguageInformal LogicFormal ProofProof TheoryProof TheoryMathematical PracticeQuasi-empiricism In MathematicsMathematical FolklorePhilosophy Of MathematicsMathematics As A LanguageHistory Of LogicGeometryGreek MathematicsThalesHippocrates Of ChiosEudoxus Of CnidusTheaetetus (mathematician)AristotleEuclidAxiomatic MethodUndefined TermAxiomsDeductive LogicEuclid's ElementsPythagorean TheoremMathematics In Medieval IslamArithmeticAlgebraIraqi PeopleAl-HashimiIrrational NumberMathematical InductionArithmetic ProgressionAl-KarajiBinomial TheoremPascal's TriangleProof By ContradictionEuclidean GeometryParallel PostulateProof TheoryData StructureAxiomatic Set TheoryNon-Euclidean GeometryArgumentFormal ProofFormal LanguageProof TheoryIndependence (mathematical Logic)Analytic PropositionSynthetic PropositionImmanuel KantAnalytic-synthetic DistinctionMathematical BeautyPaul ErdősProofs From THE BOOKDirect ProofEven And Odd NumbersIntegerClosure (mathematics)DistributivityMathematical InductionDeductive ReasoningInductive ReasoningMaterial ConditionalInfinite SetProof By Infinite DescentSquare Root Of 2ContrapositionProof By ContrapositiveRule Of InferenceContrapositiveProof By ContradictionReductio Ad AbsurdumIrrational NumberCoprimeProof By ConstructionJoseph LiouvilleTranscendental NumberLiouville NumberCounterexampleProof By ExhaustionFour Color TheoremProbabilistic MethodProbability TheoryExistence TheoremCollatz ConjectureCombinatorial ProofBijective ProofDouble Counting (proof Technique)Nonconstructive ProofMathematical ObjectIrrational NumberRational NumberStatistical ProofPure MathematicsCryptographyNumber TheoryMathematical StatisticsComputer-assisted ProofFour Color TheoremParallel PostulateEuclidean GeometryZermelo-Fraenkel Set TheoryList Of Statements Undecidable In ZFCGödel's Incompleteness TheoremExperimental MathematicsEudoxus Of CnidusEuclidFoundational MathematicsMathematical ObjectsExperimental MathematicsFractal GeometryProof Without WordsPythagorean TheoremZhoubi SuanjingMissing Square PuzzleElementary ProofNumber TheoryComplex AnalysisPrime Number TheoremEnlargeMathematical ObjectsDataStatistical ProofStatisticsData AnalysisBayesian AnalysisProbabilityDataPhysicsMathematical Methods Of PhysicsParticle PhysicsExperimentObservational StudyPhysical CosmologyScatter PlotsInductive LogicBayesian AnalysisInductive LogicProbabilityCertaintyMathematical InductionBayes' TheoremBayesian ProbabilityEvidenceInformationPsychologismLanguage Of ThoughtPhilosopherGottfried Wilhelm LeibnizFregeCarnapLanguage Of ThoughtEmpirical ScienceWikipedia:Citation NeededSpinozaCertaintyDescartesCogito Ergo SumQ.E.D.LatinWikipedia:Citation NeededTombstone (typography)EponymPaul HalmosPortal:LogicPortal:MathematicsAutomated Theorem ProvingInvalid ProofList Of Incomplete ProofsList Of Long ProofsList Of Mathematical ProofsNonconstructive ProofProof By IntimidationTermination AnalysisWhat The Tortoise Said To AchillesBill Casselman (mathematician)International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-470-45793-7International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-03-029558-0The BibleNew York Academy Of SciencesDigital Object IdentifierRutgers UniversitySamuel BussSamuel BussInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/9780080533186Probabilistic AlgorithmDavid MumfordIndra's Pearls (book)Wayback MachineGeorge PólyaMathematics And Plausible ReasoningJames Franklin (philosopher)International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-646-54509-4Wiley PublishingInternational Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-471-68058-3International Standard Book NumberSpecial:BookSources/0-521-67599-5Template:LogicTemplate Talk:LogicLogicOutline Of LogicHistory Of LogicArgumentation TheoryAxiologyCritical ThinkingLogic In Computer ScienceMathematical LogicMetalogicMetamathematicsNon-classical LogicPhilosophical LogicPhilosophy Of LogicSet TheoryAbductive ReasoningAnalytic–synthetic DistinctionAntinomyA Priori And A PosterioriDeductive ReasoningDefinitionDescriptionInductive ReasoningInferenceLogical FormLogical ConsequenceLogical TruthNameNecessity And SufficiencyMeaning (linguistics)ParadoxPossible WorldPresuppositionProbabilityReasonReferenceSemanticsStatement (logic)Strict ConditionalSubstitution (logic)Syntax (logic)TruthValidityIndex Of Logic ArticlesList Of Mathematical Logic TopicsList Of Boolean Algebra TopicsList Of Set Theory TopicsList Of LogiciansList Of Rules Of InferenceList Of ParadoxesList Of FallaciesList Of Logic SymbolsPortal:LogicCategory:LogicWikipedia:WikiProject LogicWikipedia Talk:WikiProject LogicHelp:CategoryCategory:Mathematical LogicCategory:Mathematical TerminologyCategory:Mathematical ProofsCategory:Sources Of KnowledgeCategory:Webarchive Template Wayback LinksCategory:Articles Containing Potentially Dated Statements From 2011Category:All Articles Containing Potentially Dated StatementsCategory:All Articles With Unsourced StatementsCategory:Articles With Unsourced Statements From November 2014Category:Articles With Unsourced Statements From October 2017Discussion About Edits From This IP Address [n]A List Of Edits Made From This IP Address [y]View The Content Page [c]Discussion About The Content Page [t]Edit This Page [e]Visit The Main Page [z]Guides To Browsing WikipediaFeatured Content – The Best Of WikipediaFind Background Information On Current EventsLoad A Random Article [x]Guidance On How To Use And Edit WikipediaFind Out About WikipediaAbout The Project, What You Can Do, Where To Find ThingsA List Of Recent Changes In The Wiki [r]List Of All English Wikipedia Pages Containing Links To This Page [j]Recent Changes In Pages Linked From This Page [k]Upload Files [u]A List Of All Special Pages [q]Wikipedia:AboutWikipedia:General Disclaimer



view link view link view link view link view link